Up: Issue 5 Next: Paper 2

Voting matters - Issue 5, January 1996

Estimating the Probability of Monotonicity Failure in a UK General Election

Dr C Allard

Crispin Allard holds a PhD in statistics from the University of Warwick, and is a member of the ERS Council.

1. Summary

Three years ago, the Plant Report rejected STV as a system worth considering for elections to the House of Commons, citing evidence submitted by Michael Dummett (based on an example originating from Reference [2]) on the grounds that it could be non-monotonic. In this paper I attempt to estimate the probability of a monotonicity failure which affects the number of seats won by a party. I estimate the probability of this occurring in a multi-member constituency in one election as: 2.5 × 10**(-4), equivalent to less than once every century across the whole UK. [This result was first reported in Reference [1] as 2.8 × 10**(-4). I have revised this down as a result of a refinement in the method.]

2. Representing the problem

Consider an n-member STV constituency, in which n-1 candidates have so far been elected, and the three remaining candidates (denoted A, B and C), one each from the Conservative, Labour and Liberal Democrat Parties are competing for the final place. The conditions for monotonicity failure are as follows:
  1. A is ahead of B, and B is ahead of C;
  2. When C is eliminated, his transfers put B ahead of A, so that B is elected;
  3. If a number of voters switch their relevant preference from A to C, so that both A and C are ahead of B, then when B is eliminated, A is ahead of C, so that A is elected;
for any ordering of A, B and C.

Writing these conditions down in mathematical terms we get:

  1. a > b > c.
  2. a < b + alpha×c.
  3. There exists x such that:
where (alpha and beta can be considered as the level of advantage which one party can expect to gain over another as a result of the exclusion of a candidate from a third party). The following conditions are equivalent to 1-3 above: Using barycentric coordinates (and denoting each point of the triangle to represent one candidate having all the votes), these conditions are illustrated in figure 1.

Figure 1

Thus, if we assume a uniform distribution, the probability of this type of monotonicity failure is the ratio of the area of the small triangle (either PQR or STR, whichever is the smaller) to the area of the large one (ABC). To see why we must take the smaller triangle, note that to satisfy condition M3, a point in Figure 1 must be below both the lines:

a = (2 + beta)b - c and a= 2b - c.

Note that if beta > alpha, conditions M1-M3 cannot simultaneously be satisfied, so in this case we define: Area (STR) = 0.

Switching to Cartesian coordinates,

x = c + b/2

y = sqrt(3) × b/2

the areas of the three triangles are found to be:

Area(ABC) = sqrt(3)/4

Area(PQR) =

Area(STR) =

= 0 otherwise

So if we let p be the probability of monotonicity failure, we can find its value as follows:

else p=0

Or, by substituting, gamma = max{alpha, beta, 0} delta = max{min{alpha, beta}, 0}

we obtain a single equation for p: (P1)

3. Estimating the transfer patterns

Clearly we need to know the likely pattern of transfers between candidates from different parties, which requires access to the ballot papers of a typical British electorate voting by STV for real political parties. Last year an ERS/MORI exit poll of 3,983 London voters was conducted during the European Parliament elections, in which they were asked to cast preferential votes in two multi-member constituencies. The results form by far the best available data on the likely behaviour of British voters in an election conducted by STV.

Details of the poll may be found in Reference 3, which includes tables of terminal transfers (transfers of votes from a candidate whose party has no further candidates left who are still eligible to receive votes). Unfortunately, there is no terminal data from Conservative candidates, since none occurred in the count of the mock vote, so this data cannot be used.

Instead I try to consider all the possible transfers of votes which could have taken place. For each of the two constituencies (London North and London South), and for every ordered triple of candidates (Conservative, Labour, Lib Dem), the following data extracted from the poll results is used.

The number of votes which would transfer to the Labour candidate (if the Conservative were to be eliminated leaving only the Labour and Lib Dem candidates); the number which would transfer to the Lib Dem candidate in such circumstances; and the number which would be non-transferable.

This data is repeated for the each of the Labour and Lib Dem candidates being eliminated, providing 840 data sets (sadly not independent!) on which to base the estimate of transfer patterns, and hence estimate p. The number of data sets arises from 216 ordered triples in London North (6-seater), 64 in London South (4-seater), and three data sets for each ordered triple.

4. Method

In outline, I employ the following method (using an Excel spreadsheet): So, if the UK is divided into 138 multi-member constituencies, as proposed in Reference 4, and assuming an average of one General Election every four years, we would expect one instance of final-stage monotonicity failure affecting party standing under STV roughly every 115 years.

5. Justifying the approach

The problem of estimating the probability of monotonicity failure under STV is complicated, involving political considerations and statistical judgement as well as pure mathematics. So inevitably I have had to make a number of assumptions and simplifications. I will now attempt to identify all the potential objections to my approach and answer some of the possible criticisms.

5.1 Only monotonicity failure affecting parties is considered.

It is almost certainly true that the probability of affecting individual candidates within a party is much greater. For a start, far more voters are prepared to transfer within a party than between parties. This is supported if we look at ERS Council Elections (which are like elections between candidates of the same party since all support electoral reform), where potential instances have been observed.

Nevertheless, given that STV is the only system which even attempts to represent intra-party opinion, any minor 'imperfection' in this respect is irrelevant to the choice of an electoral system. And it is certainly the case that most of the opponents of STV are far more concerned with party representation.

Finally, it is a necessary simplification since intra-party transfer patterns are notoriously unpredictable and difficult to model.

5.2 The model only covers three parties and final-stage transfers.

Of course, earlier stages and a greater number of parties allow more opportunities for monotonicity failure. However, I claim that the probability of this making a difference to the final result is tiny compared to the figure I have calculated above.

To see this, consider the diagram in figure 1. The effect is only possible when there are three candidates with very similar votes (Q is the geometric centre). Thus, if there are four candidates competing for the final place, a candidate who 'benefits' in the penultimate stage is still very unlikely to benefit in terms of election (and one who 'loses' probably would not have been elected anyway).

If there are four candidates competing for two places, with three in danger of elimination, then the fourth may be discounted (as a certainty), and we are back to the original problem. Only in the case where there are four or more candidates all with similar votes might a relevant situation arise; it is reasonable to ignore such nth order terms.

5.3 The method assumes a Uniform (prior) distribution of votes between the three parties.

This assumes that the three parties each have the same marginal distribution. In a one-member constituency this is highly unlikely, but in a multi-member constituency the relevant distribution to consider is the remainder, once n-1 seats have been 'allocated', and the appropriate number of quotas deducted from each party's vote.

Therefore, in order for the assumption to be reasonable, all we need is to have across the country three parties capable of achieving proportions of votes over a range of at least one quota. This would typically be achieved by a party receiving 10% or more of the national (or regional) vote.

A similar principle is at work behind the Wichmann-Hill pseudo-random generator, where the sum of a number of variables is known to tend to normality, but the fractional part of the sum remains rectangular. There is room here for someone to conduct a proper analysis, which I am confident would uphold my assumption.

5.4 The results are based on an opinion poll conducted only in London.

This represents probably the biggest area of doubt about the result and, since this is the best data available so far, there is no way of avoiding it. The STV ballot paper was constructed by listing (nearly) all candidates in each of the Euro-constituencies represented. Since this was an election for MEPs, recognition of most individual candidates must have been relatively low.

However, we can only speculate on how voters would react in a General election conducted by STV, and it is by no means obvious that voting patterns would be substantially different. The same applies to the London factor. While the relative positions of the parties would vary across the country, there is no reason to suppose that the nature of voting patterns would be any different.

5.5 Why has shrinkage been applied in this way?

Shrinkage is one of the results of Bayesian analysis which has been accepted by non-Bayesian statisticians as representing a true effect which does not appear in more traditional models. I have judged that a hierarchical model is relevant to this situation, so we must take account of shrinkage. A reference will be given in the next issue of Voting matters to provide an explanation of shrinkage for non-statisticians.

If the charge is that I have not defined a full Bayesian hierarchical model, with detailed multivariate prior distributions etc., then I plead guilty. This was done deliberately to avoid specifying prior distributions which might obscure the argument. The value of t is arbitrary but, I believe, reasonable. A little sensitivity analysis shows that it does not affect the final result by more than a tenth.

5.6 The weightings used in the final calculation do not allow for some votes having a greater effect.

Rather than try to work out what effect the voting patterns might have had in this particular election, I wanted to gain an estimate of overall voting patterns. This means considering both first and last place candidates, since in different constituencies each party will have somewhere between 0 and 5 'safe' seats, so the candidate involved in a three-way battle could be anyone between the first and sixth most popular in that party.

The best way to cope with such uncertainty is to assign equal weightings to each elector.

6. Conclusions

Using the best data available and using reasonable assumptions I have estimated the probability that monotonicity failure would arise in a UK General Election conducted by STV. That probability turns out to be extremely small. In political terms it may as well be zero. Opponents of STV will need to come up with better reasons if they wish to reject it out of hand.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Professor Shaun Bowler of the University of California at Riverside for his help in supplying data from the ERS/MORI poll, and to Richard Wainwright and others for their encouragement and interest in this research.

References

  1. Crispin Allard, 'Lack of Monotonicity - Revisited', Representation 33:2 (1995), pp48-50.
  2. G. Doron and R. Kronick, American Journal of Political Science 21, pp303-311.
  3. Shaun Bowler and David M. Farrell, 'A British PR Election: Testing STV with London's Voters', Representation 32:120 (1994/5), pp90-3.
  4. Robert A. Newland, Electing the United Kingdom Parliament, 3rd Edition (ERS, 1992).

Appendix: Summary Statistics

Below is a table showing the transfer trends in North and South London. The transfers are weighted means, expressed as percentages of the respective first preference votes. The advantages (corresponding to alpha or beta) are given after adjusting for shrinkage. See section 4 for a full explanation. Each party is shown with the number of first preference votes cast in the poll for candidates of that party.

Of the 3,983 voters polled, 3,013 expressed a valid first preference for a candidate from one of the three main parties, of whom 1,778 were from North London and 1,235 from South London. The overall probabilities of monotonicity failure were found to be 0.00013 in North London and 0.00043 in South London, giving a (weighted) mean of 0.00025 and a sample variance of 2 × 10**(-8).


Up: Issue 5 Next: Paper 2